Reviews

Einstein's Revolution: A Study Of Theory Unification by Rinat M. Nugayev

drjonty's review against another edition

Go to review page

3.0

I enjoyed this but it was necessarily inconclusive.

mandolyte's review against another edition

Go to review page

5.0

Great read! I think Smolin's sense of things has the ring of truth, but, please, I'm less than an amateur.
- that QM is incomplete and that realism will win-out
- that time is fundamental and space is emergent.

Two links:
http://backreaction.blogspot.com/2019/06/a-conversation-with-lee-smolin-about.html
http://backreaction.blogspot.com/2019/06/book-review-einsteins-unfinished.html

This is also the first completed book where I used a book log (https://bulletjournal.com/blogs/bulletjournalist/book-log). See my comment to that article to see how I modified the presented technique to suit me.

emmy9937's review against another edition

Go to review page

Not up for reading about quantum physics right now. Will try again some other time

campychick001's review against another edition

Go to review page

2.0

This book is basically an analysis of various theorems and gaps in knowledge in the world of quantum physics. Aside from the technical science, the main take away from this book is the importance of scientific advancement. Specifically, the idea that there is no cookie cutter way to achieve this - and that sometimes unconventional methods are those that produce the greatest results. I was also intrigued by his commentary on the state of the scientific and academic community and their reticence to go against the grain and fear of failure.

I am quite impressed with the author's ability to simplify these advanced topics by cutting back on jargon (when possible) and using basic analogies and figures to get some points across. Although the author did a pretty good job of describing these technical topics to the layperson, I still think the reader may need a more advanced background in science/physics to understand some of the topics discussed - there were several instances where he lost me for a bit. I do appreciate the inclusion of footnotes, a basic glossary, references, and a list of further recommended readings. Although I love all things science, physics is not at the top of my list or expertise. I appreciated the content presented and learned some new things but this was not the most enjoyable reading experience for me. If you are really into physics, I think would enjoy this book.

mihnea_cateanu's review against another edition

Go to review page

challenging informative medium-paced

3.75

jwpeddle's review against another edition

Go to review page

4.0

Solid lay-accessible explanation of what we know about quantum behaviour and the pros and cons of existing models for the unknown. Lee Smolin in staunchly realist and comes off a bit dismissive in the early book, but I think he gives fair platform to the many ideas he's unhappy with before pitching his own fascinating one.

kahawa's review against another edition

Go to review page

2.0

What I liked: he's enthusiastic, willing to challenge the status quo. Um, that's about it.

What I disliked: he doesn't understand Quantum Physics. Sophistical of me to say so, I know, since no one understands QP (a la Feynman). Maybe I should say he doesn't understand the Copenhagen Interpretation.

I'm going to expose my ignorance here and just write as though I know what I'm talking about. This is, after all, where I journal my thoughts, not create NYT book reviews. I don't really know what I'm talking about though.

I liked Smolin's books in the past, but this one was seriously obtuse. I couldn't track with him very well. His example about a dog and cat lover and something about politics just didn't work. It came across as a mathematician trying to put maths into words, which often doesn't go well. There were so many sentences too that just didn't make sense. That's probably partly my fault, since physics isn't my speciality. But I've read enough books on physics to know how to track with these, and I didn't track with these.

Now for the biggie. Smolin writes as though QP is a theory about what is, when I think it's a theory about what we can actually say/know. QP boils down to the observer problem, which means that no experiment can truly test a theory, ever, because theories assume a god's eye view, but all real world experiments interact with their theories in feedbacky loopy kinds of ways. In philosophical terms, this is equivalent to trying to prove one's own sanity. You can't do it, without assumptions, and those assumptions can't be verified. Physics is incomplete because observers will never truly understand the system of which they themselves are a part. It sucks. I grew up committed to the idea of objective truth, and objective reality. Now I think it's pointless to talk about it. I feel like Smolin hasn't grasped this, and he's still trying to prove that we're all sane and there is an objective reality. We'll never be able to know.

I don't think that Schroedinger's cat is about a cat actually being in a superposition, or actually being dead and alive until there's a 'measurement'. I think the theory implies that there's no way, ever, to know if the cat is dead or alive until we do the measurement. There's no back door, or god's eye knowledge, that can get us around that. Einstein wanted there to be a way, and kept trying to come up with ways. But Bohr kept showing him how he was 'cheating', and that his theories always left a step incomplete. I was cheering for Einstein for a long time. Now I think, frustratingly, that Bohr saw more clearly.

Oh, and the other thing that I think that Smolin gets completely wrong, is that he says that the Copenhagen Interpretation claims that 'measurements' are special. I hear this a lot, and sometimes I hear it from woo spiritualists who think that consciousness is special and brings worlds into existence and things like that. I think Smolin has it backwards. I think that Realists (like Smolin and Einstein et al) discount measurements. They forget that every experiment must include the act of measuring the results, and measurements are physical processes. In Einstein's thought experiments, he was doing the measurement by 'magic', that is, by measuring in his head from a god's eye view. But you can't do that in 'reality'. For the theory to have real world application, it can't leave out a part that impacts the experiment, and measurements impact experiments. Once you realise that, you have to measure the measurement. And measure the measurement of that measurement. And so on ad infinitum. Which means, you can never really complete an experiment. Which is what's so frustrating about QP.

It goes like this: let's do an experiment. OK, done, now let's find out what happened - the theorist just 'knows' what happened by doing magic metaphysical thoughts, but the experimenter has to send a grubby beam of light into the results, which are now the results that include the grubby beam of light. This would be fine on the macro scale (measurements wash out), but when we're trying to find out about beams of light, we have to calculate how the grubby beam of light affected the results, and we don't know how to do that because if we test the grubby beam of light, we're sending yet another gubby beam of light at it. It's like trying to tell how firm an avocado is, so you keep pushing on it, but you're not sure if it's squishy because you're squeezing it, or because it was already squishy. So you squeeze it some more to see when it stops getting squishy.

It's not that QP is incomplete, it's that epistemology is incompletable. It's Gödels all the way down.

At least, this is where I'm at with QP at the moment. I might be completely wrong.

bakudreamer's review against another edition

Go to review page

Actually painful to read a lot of this, but, there it is

daire_'s review against another edition

Go to review page

challenging informative slow-paced

3.0

blackoxford's review against another edition

Go to review page

3.0

Do Scientists Make Good Philosophers?

I am confused. Not (inordinately) by quantum physics: Smolin is an excellent populariser of an almost impossible subject. But by his philosophy, which appears self-contradictory. Either I don’t understand his philosophical argument or he doesn’t. Either way, it’s not a terribly convincing exposition of his point of view.

Smolin begins in a way that makes my heart sing: “To explain the world to ourselves we make up stories and then, because we are good storytellers, we get infatuated by them and confuse our representations of the world with the world itself. This confusion afflicts scientists as much as laypeople; indeed, it affects us more, because we have such powerful stories in our tool kits.” A scientist who takes seriously the centrality of story-telling to everything connected with human beings is a rare and beautiful bird.

He then increases my admiration by recognising the essentially conventional character of not just science but all human inquiry: “To have a scientific mind is to respect the consensus facts, which are the resolution of generations of dispute, while maintaining an open mind about the still unknown.” Some people know more than others about certain things, like physics. Groups of these people argue continuously about what they know about those things. Their concurrence is the best view, for the moment, that we’re likely to have about those things, even if the unknown remains... well, unknown.

And finally, Smolin recognises the validity of what I call metaphysics or what others think of as religion, that intellectual realm beyond language and beyond at least current experience. “It helps to have a humble sense of the essential mystery of the world, for the aspects that are known become even more mysterious when we examine them further.” In many ways the mystery of the ‘beyond’ increases the more we know. Existence itself, we begin to realise, is not something we are able to measure and evaluate. The closer we get to this descriptor-which-is-not-a-property, the less sure we are about everything else. So that “The simplest facts about our existence and our relationship to the world are mysteries.”

But then Smolin starts to get a bit eccentric. He says, “Behind the century-long argument over quantum mechanics is a fundamental disagreement about the nature of reality—a disagreement which, unresolved, escalates into an argument about the nature of science.” But he has already implied that he doesn’t want to fight about reality but rather who has a better story. It is at this point that he gets swept into metaphysics not as a scientist, or even merely as a thinker, but as a polemicist, that is, someone with an ideological axe to grind, with a story that he takes to be more than a story. He wants to tell me, and you, and his fellow scientists what’s really there. And it is here that we part company.*

Smolin‘s world is divided between realists, people like him who believe that there is a world that exists independently of our experience of it; and purported anti-realists, those who believe that our knowledge of the world, particularly our knowledge of atoms, radiation and elementary particles, is not just a matter of convention but ONLY a matter of convention. That is to say, that what we know about is solely the language in which we know it, and that’s the end of the matter. He claims that most scientists today are anti-realists and that this attitude represents a kind of ideology which is inhibiting a solution to the big problems of contemporary quantum physics.

This distinction between realists and anti-realists, however, is a parody and a slur; and in the context of his argument, it is fraudulent. To understand why, it is necessary to define metaphysics a little more carefully. Immanuel Kant, the 18th century thinker, is the go-to guy when it comes to what we mean by metaphysics in the modern world. For Kant, metaphysics is not about religious revelation or mythical accounts about how the world came into being. Rather it is a purely rational endeavour for discovering what might lie beyond language, beyond our immediate experience and what allows us to connect the two. Our experience is certainly of reality; it’s the getting of that experience into language which causes the disjunction between reality and story.

The intellectual technique which Kant developed for metaphysical inquiry is called Transcendental Deduction. In simple terms this technique tries to establish what things must be the case in order for us to connect our experiences with the language we use to express that experience. These ‘transcendentals’ are things that we employ instinctively as human beings to make sense of what we casually call reality. Since we cannot even conceive of something called reality without them, however, we are never able to communicate about reality itself, only reality filtered or constructed through this human faculty. Since communication about this reality can only take place through language, we are constantly tempted, as Smolin admits, to confuse language with reality.

Even these transcendentals are parts of stories however. Kant suggested, for example, that reality must have certain characteristics if it were to appear to us as it does, even through our human filters. Space and time, he said, are two such characteristics. These are the kind of things that must be there in light of our experience. But about a century after he wrote, it became clear that he was wrong. It is not space and time that are elements of reality, but space-time, an entirely different metaphysical, as well as scientific category. Space-time is part of a contrasting story. As such it is yet another deduction about the world, not necessarily a ‘thing’ in the world. It is a word, a concept, that is connected to other words and concepts, and not to that vague unknown called reality.

And Smolin is undoubtedly correct: something is missing from current quantum theory. Perhaps, as he suggests, time generates space, which might then explain quantum entanglement. But neither Kant nor any other ‘idealist’ thinker, scientist or layperson, would deny the existence of reality as something independent of human perception or experience. What they are likely to deny is that the language we use to express this reality is ever any kind of permanent truth. Among other things, our deductions about what is actually ‘there’ are changing more or less continuously. And we know that the language we use to describe what is there, however scientific, is not the reality of what is there. The map is not the territory. Smolin’s story may turn out to be better by the standards of his colleagues but it will never be any more real.

Regardless of its elusiveness, indeed its inherent unattainability, reality is a necessary transcendental category for all scientific inquiry. Perhaps it is the only one that really matters. Without a presumption that there is something ‘there’ to be inquired about, inquiry would not take place. Without the failure of scientific stories to achieve what we hope to achieve, knowledge could not be distinguished from self-interested boast. Reality is a permanently receding horizon which doesn’t get any nearer the more precise our measurements or the more inclusive our theories become. To even suggest that some scientists claim that reality doesn’t exist is simply a tendentious ploy on Smolin’s part. It’s a ridiculous assertion. And it needlessly undermines his own position.

It is perfectly possible and respectable for scientists to differ about the best transcendental deductions to be made about reality. Or indeed for scientists to simply decline to make such deductions and ‘get on with calculating.’ And there are better and worse deductions to be made depending upon how inclusive they are of alternative deductions, that is to say, scientific stories about the world. Smolin’s story isn’t one of these; it is only about the possibility of one of these - that he apparently wants assistance in writing. He claims his story might be better once it gets finished. Sure, and I might have been a world-wide celebrity with Stephen Hawking’s intellect and Rock Hudson’s looks. Shoulda, woulda, coulda, as my mother used to say. Until his story is told, it has no status except that of dream.

The literary parallel is to me inescapable: Can you imagine a Jane Austen who instead of exposing the misogynistic mores of contemporary English culture in her work, wrote instead about the reprehensible lack of critical fiction among contemporary authors and solicited allies in her cause for ‘real’ fiction? Or perhaps a Cervantes who instead of creating the genre of the novel, complained about the absence of untrue but meaningful narratives about human beings trapped in their own imaginings? I think it’s clear that neither of these imaginary figures would be taken seriously by history.

So despite his overtly Kantian epistemology, which makes the distinction between stories and reality, what it is that Smolin wants to replace current quantum mechanics, is at best only something temporarily better not something definitive, true or even necessarily a closer approximation to reality. Instead of slinging intellectual mud, perhaps he just ought to get on with it. I regret my conclusion because Smolin is a fan of Leibniz, as am I; but he’s not doing himself or Leibniz justice with this fruitless rant about realism.**

=====================

* Smolin contradicts his initial assertions about science both implicitly and explicitly throughout the book. Here is one example:
“I want to uncover a world beyond quantum mechanics. Where quantum mechanics is mysterious and confusing, this deeper theory will be entirely comprehensible. I can make this claim because we have known since the invention of quantum mechanics how to present the theory in a way that dissolves the mysteries and resolves the puzzles. In this approach, there is no challenge to our usual beliefs in an objective reality, a reality unaffected by what we know or do about it, and about which it is possible to have complete knowledge. In this reality, there is just one universe, and when we observe something about it, it is because it is true. This can justly be called a realist approach to the quantum world.”

Note the sudden appearance of ‘complete knowledge’ and ‘truth’ and the disappearance of ‘mystery’. Smolin clearly reckons he is on the trail of ultimate reality itself. Note also that he is particularly concerned not to challenge our ‘common-sensical’ beliefs. Yet in the previous paragraph he wants us to dump our common sense understanding of what physicists call ‘locality,’ that is, the impossibility of two objects sharing properties at a distance. So much for the distinction between stories and reality.

** inspired by Leibniz, Smolin imagines a universe of entities called ‘nads’ which are similar to Leibniz’s ‘monads’. These nads are defined relationally to each other, an idea perhaps borrowed from the Christian doctrine of the Trinity in which each Person is defined entirely in terms of its relations to the other two. Nads are ‘events’ rather than things in Smolin’s conception. Interestingly, this idea has been previously put forth by Philip Caputo in his Theology of the Event. See: https://www.goodreads.com/review/show/693643721?book_show_action=false&from_review_page=1

But this idea makes no sense in terms of Leibniz’s Monadology since each of his monads is ‘windowless,’ that is, has no perception of anything but it’s own isolated state. The only relation the monad has is with God. The monad’s perception is in fact supplied entirely by God who also ensures that the collectivity of monads is coordinated in their perceptions and actions. Smolin seems dangerously close to this theology when he suggests that there are ‘hidden connections’ among nads which defy locality restrictions and explain quantum entanglement. That may be interesting poetry but it is not compelling science... or theology.